Christianity’s fundamental promise is of eternal life, and the risk of refusing to accept God’s grace is generally accepted to be eternal damnation. While the truth of these statements is still subject to debate, there is little empirical evidence of the benefit of eternal life, and little research exploring the possible drawbacks of a decision to forego evil in exchange for the promise of eternal salvation. In a world of finite resources, decisions about how best to dispose of available resources while alive need to take into account the long-term and (if certain cosmological properties are shown to hold) potentially eternal consequences of the choice between good and evil. In this blog post, we will examine the costs and benefits of baptism and rejection of sin from an econometric standpoint. Of specific interest in this blog post is the relationship between the benefits of accepting God’s grace and the discount rate society applies to years of life not yet lived.
The immediate use of an analysis of the costs and benefits of accepting god’s grace is obvious, but from a wider perspective a clear understanding of the economic aspects of this theological decision may help us to understand the persistence of evil in a world where humans have free will, and to answer the eternal question: why does evil exist in a world shaped according to God’s will?
Methods
Standard cost-effectiveness analysis methods were applied to two simple decision problems. The first decision problem is the question of whether or not to baptize a child, on the assumption that baptism grants the child God’s grace, causing them to live a holy life but to lose the benefits that might accrue to an evil-doer. The analysis was then extended to consider a problem implicit in a great deal of modern rhetoric about the soul and sexuality, viz: if homosexuality is a choice, and that choice leads only to hell, is it cost-effective to choose to be homosexual? This question was answered in terms of numbers of partners foregone, and quality-adjusted life years gained from the sacrifice.
The basic decision problem: whether to baptize
The basic decision problem was addressed using standard measures of effectiveness. It was assumed that were a child to be baptized they would be eligible to enter heaven upon their death, and would thus be able to live forever. Were they not to be baptized, they are assumed to enter hell at death. Each year of life lived was assumed to grant the individual a full quality adjusted life year (QALY); each year in heaven (from now until the rapture, i.e. infinite years from now) was also assumed to grant 1 QALY; while entry into hell was considered to grant 0 QALYs. All QALYs were discounted using the standard formula, and the effect of the discounting rate on the benefits of each decision were calculated over three different life expectancies: 45 years (enlightenment-era), 70 years (biblical lifespan) and 80 years (the life expectancy granted by modern materialist living). Effectiveness was then assessed for a wide range of discount rates, varying from 0.5% to 5%. The difference in QALYs gained (the incremental effect) was then calculated for all these scenarios.
Cost-effectiveness calculation for the baptism problem
Having calculated the incremental effect of baptism, the cost was then calculated under the assumption that evil people make more money. This assumption is implicit in, for example, Mark 8:36, when Jesus asks
What good is it for a man to gain the whole world, yet forfeit his soul?
which suggests that doing good requires some form of material sacrifice. This is, of course, also obvious in the early doctrine of the Dominican and Franciscan orders, and much of pre-enlightenment religious debate was focused around this struggle between material goods and goodness.
This contrast was modeled by a variable , which represents the percentage of additional annual income an unbaptized sinner earns relative to a person living in grace. For example, if a sinner earns 10% more than a convert, then
. Then, assuming a fixed average income for god-fearing individuals, we can calculate the lost income due to being good. This is the incremental cost of salvation. From this calculated incremental cost and the incremental benefit, we can estimate an incremental cost effectiveness ratio (ICER), and estimate whether the decision to baptize is cost-effective.
In keeping with standard practice as used by, for example, the National Institute for Health and Clinical Excellence, we set the basic income of one of the saved to be the mean income of the UK, and define baptism as “cost-effective” if its ICER falls below a threshold of three times the annual mean income of the UK. We also establish a formula for the cost-effectiveness of salvation, based on the relative difference in income between the good and the evil, the discount rate, and the human lifespan.
All income in future years was discounted in the same way as future QALYs.
The costs and benefits of voluntary homosexuality
Finally, we address a problem implicit in some forms of modern christian rhetoric, that of the wilful homosexual. Many religious theorists seem to think (either implicitly or openly) that homosexuality is a choice. If so, then the choice can be modeled in terms of an exchange of sexual partners for eternal damnation. In this analysis, we calculated the number of sexual partners a potentially homosexual male will forego over a 20 year sexual career commencing at age 15. We assumed that all life years before age 15 are irrelevant to the calculation (that is, we assumed that all individuals make a choice at age 15 as to whether to be good or evil), and that a person foregoing homosexuality will have 0 partners. Other assumptions are the same as those made above. The ICER for being good was then calculated as the cost in foregone sexual partners (discounted over a wide range of rates) divided by the QALYs gained through foregoing this lifestyle and gaining access to heaven.
Faustian discount rates and the problem of heavenly utilities
Commonly used discount rates range from 3 to 5%, but these are potentially inconsistent with the discount rates preferred by evil-doers. In this study we did not model differential discount rates between evil-doers and the elect, but we did consider one special case: that in which everyone observes a discount rate equal to that observed by Dr. Faust. As is well known, Dr. Faust sold his soul to Mephistopheles in exchange for earthly power, and after 24 years his soul was taken into hell. Since he knew the time frame at the beginning of the deal, this implies that he was following a discount rate sufficient to rate all time more than 24 years in the future at 0 value. Under standard discounting practice such a rate does not exist, but we can approximate it by the rate necessary to value all time more than 24 years in the future at no more than 5% of current value. This discount rate, which we refer to as the Faustian Discount Rate, is approximately 12.5%. All scenarios were also tested under this discount rate.
A further problem is the problem of calculating utility weights for a year spent in heaven or hell. Given the lack of empirical data on utility of a year in heaven, and the paucity of first hand accounts, we assumed that a year in heaven was equivalent to a year without pain or suffering of any kind, i.e. one full QALY. According to the site What Christians Want to Know, Revelations 4:8 describes heaven as
a constant chant of holy angels that are continually proclaiming Holy, Holy, Holy over the throne of God. The Mercy Seat in heaven where God sits is surrounded by magnificent angels full of glory and power that proclaim and bless the holy name of God without ceasing. Some of these are described as beasts, full of eyes, with six wings and neither rest day or night in their proclaiming the holiness of God.
For those of us who don’t enjoy doom metal, this would probably have a utility value of less than one. In the interests of a conservative analysis, we assign heaven a utility of 1.
A similar problem applies to assigning utilities for hell. Many people claim to have been to hell and back, but their accounts of their time at a Celine Dion concert are not convincing and it is unlikely that accurate data on the state of hell exists. Popular conception of hell suggests a realm of eternal torture, but it is worth noting that in standard burden of disease studies even the most unpleasant and torturous diseases – such as end states of cancer, AIDS, and severe disability – are assigned positive utility weights, often quite a lot higher than 0. It is therefore reasonable to suppose that hell should be assigned a positive but small utility. However, again in the interests of conservative analysis, we assign a utility weight of 0 to a year spent in hell – that is, it is equivalent to death.
Results
Incremental benefit of salvation
The formula for the incremental benefit of salvation can be derived as
where here,
is the incremental benefit of being good, in QALYs
- r is the discount rate
- l is the human life expectancy
Figure 1 charts this incremental benefit over a wide range of discount rates for three different life expectancies.
It is clear that as the discount rate increases the incremental benefit of salvation decreases rapidly. At the Faustian Discount Rate, the incremental benefit of salvation is a mere 0.03 QALYs for a 45 year life expectancy, or 0.0004 for a human with an 80 year life expectancy. That is, even if Faustus had been offered and then rejected his bargain at birth, and expected to live to 45 years only, he would have seen the benefit to himself as being only about 0.03 years of life, due to his tendency to discount the value of years far in the future.
The cost-effectiveness of baptism
We now consider the cost-effectiveness of baptism. Let the income of one of the saved be given by , and that of an evil-doer be
. Then the income foregone in order to enter heaven is given by the formula
where all parameters are defined as before. Then the incremental cost effectiveness ratio (incremental cost divided by incremental benefit) is
The ICER is plotted in figure 2 for two common life expectancies across a range of values of the discount rate, assuming a mean annual income of 26,000 pounds and that evil-doers earn 10% more income than the saved.
At a Faustian Discount Rate, life expectancy of 70 years, and 26,000 pound mean income, the ICER for baptism is 16,202,218 pounds per QALY gained.
We can estimate a general condition on society’s discount rate for baptism to be cost-effective, in terms of the additional income gained by being evil and the life expectancy. This formula is given by:
For a life expectancy of 70 years, assuming that the damned earn 10% more than the saved, the required discount rate for baptism to be cost-effective is 4.3% or less; if the damned earn 20% more this threshold drops to 3.5%. It is clear that damnation doesn’t have to be much more materially rewarding before it becomes attractive even under quite reasonable discount rates.
The costs and benefits of voluntary homosexuality
We now consider the situation of a callow 15 year old youth, considering embarking on a life of sodomite sin. What should he choose? Obviously, from the perspective of a simple youth, the costs need to be weighed up in terms of foregone lovers. Assuming an average of five sexual partners a year, a sexual career beginning at age 15 (which is set to time 0 in this analysis) and lasting 20 years, and the same conditions on discount rates, eternal damnation, etc. as described above, a simple formula for the number of partners this man would be foregoing by refusing to choose the love that dare not speak its name can be derived as
and from this the incremental cost effectiveness ratio (measured in partners foregone per QALY gained) as
Note that this ICER is not dependent on the human lifespan. It is in fact almost linear in the discount rate (Figure 3). At the Faustian Discount Rate, the potential gay man is looking at a cost of 4.6 lovers foregone for every QALY gained. Note these values change for different annual average numbers of lovers.
It might be possible to construct an experiment that assessed individuals’ discount rates using this formula: their answers to the question “how many years of life would you give up to win an additional 5 lovers” could be used to identify their value of r.
Conclusion
In Mark 8:36, Jesus asks the rhetorical question
What good is it for a man to gain the whole world, yet forfeit his soul?
Although usually presented as a question with no clear answer, it is actually quite easy to investigate this question empirically, and to draw conclusions about its implied cost-effectiveness analysis. The results presented here show that, in general, the good gained by forfeiting one’s soul is quite great, and the decision to forego baptism and live a life of evil (including wilful homosexuality) is generally the best decision one would expect a rational actor to make. At very low life expectancies and unrealistically low discount rates it is more beneficial to forego evil and embrace salvation, but at the discount rates usually used by economists, and assumed to reflect rational decisions made by ordinary individuals, salvation is not a profitable course of action.
These findings have interesting theological implications. First, we note that the Church is most likely to gain converts in a society which has a very low discount rate – but in general, the societies where the Church first took hold were societies with high rates of infant mortality and all-cause mortality, which were likely to put a low value on the later years of life – that is, to have high discount rates. But such societies are not naturally sympathetic to the message of eternal damnation, unless they can be convinced to forego rationality in moral decision making. This might explain the Church’s historical resistance to scientific endeavour, and willingness to foment superstitious practices.
These findings also explain christianity’s historical opposition to usury. It is naturally the case that buying something today and paying for it later – i.e. borrowing – is inconsistent with a very low discount rate, which tends to value future years of lost income almost as much as now. Furthermore, usurers operating in the open market will set interest rates well above 0.05%, and it is likely that the practice of usury plus the publishing of interest rates will encourage a society with higher discount rates (in fact, it is likely that this would be encouraged by the lending class). This directly undermines the church’s lesson of salvation, which depends on very low discount rates to work.
Finally, low discount rates are often associated with environmentalism – care for future generations, priority setting that considers costs in the distant future, etc. – but on the central issue of our time (global warming) many of the born again religious organizations that most fervently preach the message of salvation also vehemently oppose any message of custodianship and environmental care. These organizations would probably make better progress in convincing people to give up the joys of the here-and-now for an indeterminate heaven (that seems to involve a lot of noise pollution) if they could find a theoretically consistent approach to discount rates.
This post has shown a simple explanation for the problem of evil: most people operate with discount rates closer to Dr. Faust than to St. Christopher, and as a result they are unlikely to accept the distant benefits of heaven over the joys of the material world. Until the church can find a way to convince us that all our tomorrows are as important as today, the problem of evil will never be solved.
November 24, 2012 at 8:09 pm
A fascinating insight, but sadly one based on a flawed model. The two flaws are:
1. In Catholicism (at least) [1] you have to factor in the ability to make a deathbed recantation. Which means anyone with a brain who has sinned and is aware of impending death will always repent and receive the full benefits. This ability is even advertised by the church. This means that projected expectations have to be adjusted to reflect the fact that sinners are )say) 90% sure they can get out jail free anyway.
2. Only mortal sins (i.e. murder) can prevent you reaching heaven. Lesser sins (such as basically all the stuff that you want to do anyway) just seem to cut the quality of seating you get in heaven. This should probably be reflected by cutting the QALY applied to heaven.
Its possible that someone will point out deathbed recantations have to be sincere to count, but we can assume that every sensible sinner will just let the fear of impending death impede their normal habits and ensure sincerity. [3]
[1] I can only speak from my experiences at Catholic schools and the associated religious classes. [2]
[2] And in 13 years of schooling, I’m only aware of one kiddie fiddler priest and a single dodgy teacher in my schools (and thankfully never my pants). So my experience may not reflect the average Catholic experience that closely.
[3] I’m quietly confident that if someone pointed a gun at my head I’d be quite able to regret pretty much anything, right down to the fact I’d be wetting my pants at that very second.
November 27, 2012 at 7:49 pm
Hmm, I didn’t want to model the vicissitudes of the Catholic religion too closely because then I thought I would have to factor in purgatory, which complicates the maths (a little) and definitely renders the benefits of Catholicism very limited. It’s interesting to note that a deathbed confession has almost zero value if purgatory for accrued sins is the consequence: purgatory must carry a heavy utility loss, and it lasts so long that the benefits of heaven will be almost zero under any standard discounting framework. So even if you analyze the cost-benefits of the deathbed confession from the point of view of the near-dead person, they’re almost zero. Obviously not zero, and largely cost-free, but still largely pointless.
I also didn’t incorporate any corporeal penalty for being christian. To quote the famous text on the matter:
If we incorporate even a small amount of such theological possibilities, baptism becomes even less cost-effective, and can even be dominated by the decision to do evil.
The model can be viewed another way, as an analysis of Dr. Faustus’ decision. He doesn’t get a deathbed recantation, since he is snatched while alive: we can compare the utility gains in life with the eternal damnation. Though there is, as I observe, a lot of controversy about the utility weight that should be applied to hell. For example, these theologians, whose body of work on the nature of sin and its punishments has achieved worldwide fame and critical acclaim, argue that hell is simply a state of insanity:
They don’t specify a utility weight[1], but it’s pretty clear that insanity is not equivalent to death and has a positive utility. So hell is better than death from a health economics perspective. But I took a conservative approach to the analysis. But any or all of these controversies would, if resolved in a less conservative way, benefit Dr. Faustus’s decision over the alternatives – especially before Martin Luther managed to do away with the idea of dispensations for sin, which basically apply a significant financial cost to being good – which I also didn’t model.
I think the conclusions are obvious if we adopt Catholic orthodoxy, especially when considering pre-reform era theology…
—
fn1: Early heavy metal was untainted by concerns about economics, or indeed anything except the purity of its theological message
November 27, 2012 at 8:04 pm
“it’s pretty clear that insanity is not equivalent to death and has a positive utility”
I think you’re still being very negative in your assessment of insanity. Either of our drinking habits would suggest that we don’t place a heavy premium on rational thought.
“the conclusions are obvious if we adopt Catholic orthodoxy, especially when considering pre-reform era theology…”
The washy post Vatican II Catholicism which got rid of purgatory or the Church of England in general are an even easier bet. For the CoE there’s a reasonable chance you can blag your way into heaven on the basis of insufficient government funding of public schooling leading you into sin.
Given the edge that gives the UK populace, Tony Blair isn’t devil. It’s just an uncanny resemblance.